A
HISTORY OF LITERARY CRITICISM—HARRY BLAMIERS
UNIT I (Bharathiar University M.Phil course)
S. Sreekumar
This is a part of the summary of
the first chapter of the book by Harry Blamiers. The rest of the summary will
be published later.
1.
THE CLASSICAL AGE
2.
THE MIDDLE AGES
3.
THE RENAISSANCE
1.
THE CLASSICAL AGE——PLATO, ARISTOTLE, HORACE, LONGINUS,
RHETORIC:
CICERO, QUINTILIAN, SENECA, PETRONIUS, MARTIANUS CAPELLA
THE
CLASSICAL AGE
Theories
propounded in the classical age have maintained their hold on the people for
many centuries.
·
In 17th
and 18th centuries writers and critics were discussing the role of
the Ancients in literary practices.
·
In 1789
Thomas Twining published a standard translation of Aristotle’s Poetics, and terms like ‘imitation’ became once more
popular in the literary circles.
·
In 1955,
the Hungarian critic Georg Lukacz1
expounded his arguments in ‘the Ideology of Modernism’ on the basis of ‘the
traditional Aristotelian dictum’ that man is a social animal. “the dictum is
applicable to all great literature, to Achilles and Werther, Oedipus and Tom
Jones, Antigone and Anna Karenina”. ***
A period
of just over a hundred years covered the lives of both Plato (c. 427-348) and
Aristotle (c.384-322). They could look back on the golden age of Pericles. They
inherited Homer & Hesiod2.
Xenophanes3 and
Herodotus4 lived
not many years before them. Greek drama was flourishing during their Age.
Aeschylus, Sophocles and Euripides together had made the fifth century the
richest age for tragic masterpieces. During the same period Aristophanes
established “a form of comedy which was to influence English writers such as
Ben Jonson and Henry Fielding”.
*** Blamiers did not mention
anything about the Neo-Aristotelian school of criticism in this piece. Actually
Neo-Aristotelian
school has popularized Aristotelian
concepts in the universities. Neo-Aristotelianism is a view of literature and
rhetorical criticism propagated by the Chicago School — Ronald S. Crane, Elder
Olson, Richard McKeon, Wayne Booth, and others
1. Georg Lukacz-- Georg
(György) Lukács (1885–1971) was a literary theorist and philosopher who is
widely viewed as one of the founders of “Western Marxism”. Lukács is best known
for his pre-World War II writings in literary theory, aesthetic theory and
Marxist philosophy. Today, his most widely read works are the Theory of the Novel of 1916 and History and Class
Consciousness of 1923.
2. Hesiod—(c. 700 bc) one of the
earliest Greek poets, often called the “father of Greek didactic poetry.” Two
of his complete epics have survived, the Theogony,
relating the myths of the gods, and the Works
and Days, describing peasant life.
3. Xenophanes—it has been claimed that literary criticism began
when Xenophanes questioned the disrespectful representation of gods in Homer
and Hesiod.
4.
Herodotus is known as the father of history. He wrote his ‘Histories’ in nine
books covering the struggle of Greece with Asia from mythical times to his own
age.
PLATO (C. 427-348)
[Among the classicists, Blamiers
begin with Plato. Questions on Plato, Aristotle, Horace & Longinus to be
expected in the examinations]
Plato
was twenty years younger than Aristophanes. He was twenty one when Sophocles
and Euripides died.
Plato
was a disciple of Socrates. He adopted the ‘Socratic’ method of question and
answer. Plato presented his teaching in dialogues, using Socrates as the
central spokesman. “Socrates lures his listeners into expressions of opinion,
then dissects them, and brings to light contradiction, absurdity, or
shallowness inherent in what they have said”. The use of this method makes for
entertaining reading, but it can mislead the inexpert reader:
1. There
is heavy irony in what Socrates says.
[Inexpert readers may not see through the irony]
2. We
cannot assume that the conclusion of Socrates is the conclusion of Plato also.
3. The
main aim of this dialectical method is to stimulate lively thinking than
indoctrination.
Plato
never assumed the role of a literary critic. In fact, he never considered
imaginative literature as something important. Because of his low estimate of
the role of imaginative literature in a healthy society, Plato ventured into
literary criticism.
In his
early dialogue Ion, Plato introduces Ion who is a rhapsodist (one who
lives by recitation of poetry). Ion recites Homer’s poetry. He is brought into
the company of Socrates who “plays with him verbally like a cat with a mouse”.
Ion claims to have special knowledge of Homer which Socrates questions.
·
If Homer
dilates on chariot driving, will not the charioteer be the best judge of his
work?
·
If Homer
dilates on medical matters, on architecture, or on fishing, will not the
physician, the architect, or the fisherman be the best judge of his work?
·
And is
not Homer’s concern with battle something a general would best understand?
·
By such
questions Socrates leads Ion to the logical conclusion that neither he nor
Homer has mastery over medicine, architecture, fishing, and the like. Poetry is
not the vehicle of learning but of inspiration.
Plato
considers inspiration as inferior to learning. Learning is an intellectual
activity. Inspiration has only an aesthetic interest. That is why Plato
dismisses literature, which is based on inspiration, in his Republic. The way in which Plato compares
the charioteers’ first hand information about chariot-driving and the poet’s
second hand information about the same define his attitude to literature. Plato
considered literature as a representation or imitation of the real thing.
However,
chariot or medicine or fishing is not the real thing for Plato. He formulated a
doctrine of Ideas, or Forms. [For example: - ‘We draw a circle. The circle may
be perfect or imperfect. But the idea of circularity which is there in our mind
before we draw the ‘circle’ is perfect. The idea is perfect. The representation
may be perfect or imperfect]
Realism
and Nominalism--
The
perfect form has priority over the imperfect appearance of it. The imperfect
form will pass away with time. For the ‘realist’ the perfect form is more important—any concept of ‘beauty’ is more important than any example of the beautiful—a beautiful flower/child etc.
For the
‘nominalist’, the
concept of beauty is abstract. It is a mere name which is given to all examples
of the beautiful. The examples are real, the concept is abstract.
“Plato’s doctrine of forms reduces the
status of what is around us”. What is around us is an inadequate representation
of what is perfect/eternal. The poet imitates what he sees around him (which is
already imperfect)
·
Idea is
the perfect thing—circularity, beauty etc.
·
What we
see around us—a circle, a beautiful flower etc. is imperfect—once removed from
reality.
·
The poet
imitates the thing he sees—circle/ beautiful flower etc. Therefore poetry is twice removed from
reality.
Plato
and Literature
Plato is
not totally insensitive to literature. He knew about the powerful appeal of
Homer. He knew about the ability of literature to move
and charm. Therefore he was suspicious
about literature. Plato believed that writers present models which will damage
rather than discipline the young. They must have courageous and noble models
presented to them in literature.
Plato
and Imitation
The
concept of imitation is very important. Through it Plato gives a questionable
status to literature—
1.
Literature is a second-hand version of life
2.
Writers are impersonators.
3.
The writer’s presentation of life is unreliable.
Thus, Plato ‘sheds around the world of
literature an aura of falsity’.
Please refer to another post on Plato in the blog. It contains additional
materials useful for the students of literature.
Dr. S. Sreekumar
Congratulation for the great post. Those who come to read your Information will find lots of helpful and informative tips. Career enhancement
ReplyDelete